One
of the basic religious questions distinguished
in the preceding chapter was the question
"What characteristics of nonhuman reality are of the greatest
significance for human
life?" Because of its special momentousness,
this question gave us a very useful basis for classifying religious
beliefs into
those that are theist and those that are
non-theist. But our purpose here is not merely to set up classifications
and distinctions,
essential as they are for any clear
discussion of religion. We want to move on to active philosophical
thinking about the
basic religious questions. Consider theism,
particularly the form of theism most familiar in our society, the belief
in a
personal and transcendent God. We want to
ask: Is this belief true? Are we justified in adopting it?
The
answer to these questions, of course,
must be reached by each individual in the
privacy of his own mind. But if he is educated and intelligent, he will
want
to reach his conclusions in the light of
serious reflection. Now, it is true that there are devout religious
people who feel
that they do not need to think
philosophically about religious questions, and some who even feel that
it is best to acquire
religious beliefs with as little
philosophical thinking as possible. This attitude presents a very
fundamental challenge
to the whole philosophical enterprise, and we
shall come back to it again, in Chapter 4. But let us begin with a
point of
view that should seem to most people both
plain and sensible. To assert that God exists is to make a very
important assertion
about reality. And at first glance, anyway,
it seems reasonable to ask whether that assertion can be justified.
In
this chapter, we shall launch a philosophical
examination of the belief in the existence of
a personal, transcendent god. A philosophical examination of a belief,
as we have seen, proceeds by asking what
reasons there are for holding it. To give a reason for any proposition
is to construct
an argument of some kind, and so we may speak
of arguments for the existence of God. We shall set forth the main
types
of argument for the existence of God, analyze
briefly those arguments that seem most convincing and instructive, and
suggest
some further lines of thought for you to
pursue. Some of these will reappear in later chapters of this book.
Others, however,
you will want to reflect on at greater length
independently, perhaps with the aid of the books and articles suggested
in the
bibliographies.
DIRECT EXPERIENCE OF GOD
The
simplest and most convincing way of knowing
the existence of anything would presumably
be to meet it in experience. How do you know that you are dizzy? Because
you
feel it. How do you know that the tree
outside your window exists? Because you see it. How do you know there is
such a thing
as mumps? Because you have had it.
Well,
perhaps the third example takes too
much for granted. You can certainly have
mumps without knowing you have it—before the doctor tells you. If the
disease
consists in being attacked by
micro-organisms, then you can't strictly see the mumps—at least not
without a microscope.
But if the symptoms of the disease are part
of it, then you can certainly feel them. The trouble with the first
example—if
there is any trouble with it—is that the
knowledge of dizziness and the feeling seem difficult to distinguish:
what
you know by the experience of dizziness is
simply that you are having the experience of dizziness. But the tree
example is
different: you have the experience of seeing
the tree, and you know that there w a tree, out there standing firmly
and solidly
by the driveway. The sight of it is what
shows you it exists. Seeing is believing.
Now
if we pause to reflect on even this simple
example, it turns out to be less simple than
it looks; but its hidden philosophical problems will have to wait until
Chapter
5. Let us for the present accept the account
as given, and say that you know the existence of the tree by seeing (and
maybe
also by touching and smelling) it. And let us
also agree, for the moment, that when you see the tree hi broad
daylight, being
sober and wide awake, with, well-tested
vision, and in a cool and detached but attentive frame of mind, you are
probably justified
in believing that the tree does exist, and
indeed in believing this with the highest degree of confidence.
§ 1. Mystic Experience
Is
there, then, a way of knowing the existence
of God that is like this I*' way of knowing
the existence of the tree—equally immediate and indubitable? Of course
God is not a physical object, and therefore
is not to be sensed. Yet there may be another kind of experience,
different from
sense experience in some ways but like it in
others, in which God is confronted directly, the way the tree seems to
be confronted
in vision. In such an experience, his
existence, and his nature to some extent, would appear to us as clearly,
as convincingly,
as compellingly as the tree appears in
daylight to the eye. According to many people, there is immediate
experience of
just this kind. And the first argument for
the existence of God that we must consider is this: we know that God
exists because
human beings have had a direct experience of
him.
Before
considering the features that this
experience is said to have by those who have
enjoyed it, it is well for us to note certain points of terminology. The
expression
"religious experience" is often used
synonymously with the expression "direct experience of God." For those
who adopt
a definition of "religion" as broad as that
set forth in the preceding chapter, this limitation of the scope of the
term "religious
experience" is unacceptable. The meaning of
the term cannot be restricted to experience of the deity of one
religious tradition.
But
within a broad category of religious
experience we must distinguish the very
important form of experience that has been called "mystic." Mystic
experience is experience
manifesting a radical difference from the
experiences of daily life. It purports to be an immediate acquaintance
with some
fundamental aspect of the nature of things
lying beyond the natural world, an authoritative intuition or
revelation; it usually
carries with it great emotional force and the
power to transform the life of the experiencer; and, though some verbal
description
of the experience can usually be given, its
full nature cannot be put into words.
Most
of the major religious traditions have
within them a strain of mystic experience,
though differing emphases and evaluations have been given to it.
Westerners will
think primarily of the celebrated Christian
religious mystics, but we should not think exclusively of them. One
distinctive
feature of satori, the experience of enlightenment in Zen Buddhism, is that despite its unique qualities the most ordinary
aspects of everyday life may serve to bring it about. Thus D. T. Suzuki writes:
The
Zen masters . . . are always found trying to avail
themselves of every apparently trivial
incident of life in order to make the disciples' minds flow into a
channel hitherto
altogether unperceived. It is like picking a
hidden lock, the flood of new experiences gushes forth from the opening.
It is
again like the clock's striking the hours;
when the appointed time comes it clicks, and the whole percussion of
sounds is
released. The mind seems to have something of
this mechanism; when a certain moment is reached, a hitherto closed
screen is
lifted, an entirely new vista opens up, and
the tone of one's whole life thereafter changes. . . . When this wiser
and deeper
world opens, everyday life, even the most
trivial thing of it, grows loaded with the truths of Zen.
The satori experience,
Suzuki continues,
is "not a conclusion to be reached by
reasoning, and defies all intellectual determination." It nevertheless
contains knowledge
of an immediate and authoritative or final
kind; but about the object of this knowledge there is nothing definite
that can
be said.
To
call this the Beyond, the Absolute, or God, or a Person
is to go further than the experience itself
and to plunge into a theology or metaphysics. . . . Perhaps the most
remarkable
aspect of the Zen experience is that it has
no personal note in it as is observable in Christian mystic experiences.1
Mystic
experience that has taken the form
of an encounter with a personal deity—the
form we shall be concerned with from now on—has occurred in various
degrees of intensity and clarity. In its
mildest or most diffuse form, it may be only the vague sense of some
Presence in
the world about us: a
feeling that there is a friendly power in nature, or an
unseen spirit who is aware of us and
concerned for us. In its most intense and compelling form, it is an
overwhelming consciousness
of communion with God, perhaps accompanied by
visual imagery and by sounds of superhuman speech. Then the
consciousness of
God becomes a transport of ecstasy, a feeling
of utter oneness with the divine, of blessedness and more than natural
aliveness.
It is an opening of a door into the beyond, a
parting of the veil of sense-experience, a white light of radiant
truth, a lifting
of the spirit into another realm. In these
and many other ways the great mystics have described their experiences
while reminding
us constantly that no words, however
profoundly symbolic and metaphorical, can convey more than a pallid
sense of what that
experience is like. Those who have had mystic
experiences in milder forms may often have been left with some doubt in
their
minds that it was really God they
experienced, but the more intense mystics have testified to the utter
conviction of God's
existence that came to them in their
experiences.
There
does not seem to be any serious doubt
that such experiences have actually occurred.
Those who have had mystic experiences generally know, of course, that
they have
had them. Others can appeal to their
testimony. Wordsworth, for example, tells us of a comparatively mild and
common form
of religious experience in "Lines Written a
Few Miles Above Tintern Abbey":
And I have felt
A presence that disturbs me with the joy
Of elevated thoughts; a sense sublime
Of something far more deeply interfused, Whose dwelling
is the light of setting suns, And the round ocean and the living air,
And the blue sky, and in the mind of man: A motion and
a spirit, that impels
All thinking things,
all objects of all thought,
And rolls through
all things.
Saint Gertrude
of Helfta (thirteenth century) testifies with evident sincerity to an experience of the intense sort:
When
then, as I have just said, Thou didst approach Thine
adorable face ... I perceived a gentle light
proceeding from Thy divine eyes and passing through mine, spreading
itself in
every secret part of me, and seeming to fill
all my members with a wonderful power and strength. At first it was as
though
it had dried up the marrow of my bones, and
then, destroying the flesh and bones themselves, as if my whole
substance were
nothing else but this divine splendor which
shone within it with greater allurement and beauty than is possible to
tell, filling
my soul with joy and incredible calmness.2
Testimony
is typically backed by deeds. For
the deeper sort of religious experience has
often left its mark upon the mystic. From the conversions of St. Paul
and St.
Augustine, for example—radical changes in
their whole way of life—we can infer that something tremendous happened
to them, something that shook them to the
roots of their personalities. And this is strong and circumstantial
evidence that
mystic experiences really do occur. The
philosophical question, however, is not whether there are mystic
experiences with
the felt characteristics described, but
whether they are a source of knowledge, a justification of belief. Now
this question
may seem impertinent after what we have just
said. And the mystic is likely to be impatient with it. If such a
soul-shattering
experience doesn't prove the existence of
God, what else could possibly prove it? When one has been through that
fire, passed
beyond that border, what more could he ask by
way of proof? As St. Teresa says,
One
who has experienced this will understand something
of it; it cannot be more clearly expressed,
since all that comes to pass in this state is so obscure. I can only say
that
the soul feels close to God and that there
abides within it such a certainty that it cannot possibly do other than
believe.3
Who, then, is the querulous philosopher,
to raise doubts about that precious certainty, so rarely attained and so highly valued?
It
must be confessed that the philosopher's
question is sometimes irritatingly ill-timed,
even when he tries to be tactful. But surely in this case its
legitimacy is
apparent. Remember that the philosopher
doesn't ask questions in a spirit of ridicule or contempt, but only
because he thinks
the problem needs looking into a little more
deeply. It is plain to all of us, when we stop to think about it, that
sometimes
we experience things that aren't so—we see,
right there before our very eyes, the lady being sawed in two, but she
isn't.
Is it possible that the mystic, too,
experiences something that isn't so? And if not, why not? That is what
the philosopher
would like to know.
But
of course, as with most philosophical
questions, this is asking a good deal. And
some philosophers have come to a skeptical conclusion. According to
them,
it is not only possible, but highly probable,
that mystic experiences are illusory—that is, what seems in them to be
true is really false. For this conclusion a
number of reasons have been given, especially these three: (1) The
number of mystics
is small compared to the remainder of the
population, and it is their word against the vast majority; therefore,
they are
like color-blind people who see gray where
there is really green. (2) Though some weight might be attached to the
reports
of mystics if they corroborated each other
completely, in fact they do not. Even the mystics within the same
religious traditions
have experienced God in so many different
ways—as unity and as trinity, as omnipotent and as finitely powerful, as
immanent
hi nature and as beyond nature, as
anthropomorphic and as non-anthropomorphic—that it seems unlikely that
they have
experienced the same God. Therefore they are
like witnesses to an automobile accident who give such different
reports
of what they saw that we cannot credit any
one of them. (3) Nearly all mystics have found that mystic experience
seldom comes
uninvited, and they have in fact worked out
elaborate techniques of preparation. But some of these techniques, such
as fasting,
sleeping on a damp stone floor, wearing hair
shirts, and various forms of self-torture, are designed to induce highly
abnormal
physiological and psychological conditions.
And what we experience under those pathological conditions, like the
hallucinations
of the advanced alcoholic or the psychotic,
are precisely what we ought most to mistrust—especially when the
strongest
wishful thinking may also be present.
We must now consider each of these objections
in turn.
§ 2. The Testimony of the Mystics
To
the first objection, that mystics are
a minority, the mystic has a definite and
plausible reply. Experiencing God happens to require certain spiritual
faculties
that most people lack, and many people who
have them lack the proper training to use them. Most people are
incapable of hearing
the individual parts in a complex fugue, but
that doesn't prove that the conductor doesn't hear them. The non-mystic
has no
positive data to contradict the mystic—he
doesn't experience the nonexistence of God (how could that be?); he
simply
has no relevant experience at all. The
analogy with color blindness is misapplied. It is not simply because the
color-blind
are in a minority that they are said to be
mistaken. It is because we can show by tests of perception that those
who have
color vision can make discriminations that
the color-blind cannot make. In the case of mysticism, it is the mystic
who
sees things that others don't. Surely if one
group is mistaken, it is more likely to be those who fail to see what
others
see.
Look
at the matter in another way. Only a
very small percentage of human beings have
been to the South Pole, or climbed the Himalayas, or orbited the earth.
Surely
they know some things—because they have seen
some things—that the rest of us don't. But we don't disbelieve what
they say just because we haven't had the
experiences ourselves. Or, better, imagine a world of people who have
all of our
senses but sight, except for a very few
gifted ones who can see as we do. Those who cannot see—the vast
majority—have
no concrete conception of what the sighted
ones experience, and there is no way the latter—call them the seers—can
make them understand. The seers claim to know
by sight things the others can never know—distant mountains, the blue
sky, the constellations of stars. Suppose
that among the sightless ones there are skeptics who use the same
argument that
is advanced against the mystic: they say the
seers are seeing things that don't exist, and that the majority must be
right.
Aren't mystics bound to be doubted by the
rest, precisely because they know uncommon truth?